The notion of category may be defined in a form which only involves morphisms and does not mention objects. This definition shows that categories are a generalization of semigroups in which the closure axiom has been weakened; rather than requiring that the product of two arbitrary elements of the system be defined as an element of the system, we only require the product to be defined in certain cases.
We define a category to be a set 1 (whose elements we shall term morphisms) and a function (which we shall term composition) from a subset of
to which satisfies the following properties:
- 1. If
are elements of such that
and
and
, then
.
- 2 If
are elements of such that
and
, then
and
and

- 3a For every
, there exists an element such that
-
and

-
and

- For all
such that
, we have
.
- 3a For every
, there exists an element such that
-
and

-
and

- For all
such that
, we have
.
This definition may also be stated in terms of predicate calculus. Defining the three place predicate by if and only if
and
, our axioms look as follows:
That a category defined in the usual way satisfies these properties is easily enough established. Given two morphisms and , the composition is only defined if
and
for suitable objects , i.e if the final object of equals the initial object of . The three hypotheses of axiom 1 state that the initial object of equals the final objects of and and that the initial object of also equals the final object of ; hence the initial object of equals the final object of so we may compose with . Axiom 2 states associativity of composition whilst axioms 3a and 3b follow from existence of identity elements.
To show that the new definition implies the old one is not so easy because we must first recover the objects of the category somehow. The observation which makes this possible is that to each object we may associate two sets: the set of morphisms which have as initial object,
, and the set of morphisms which have as final object,
. Moreover, this pair of sets
determines uniquely. In order for this observation to be useful for our purposes, we must somehow characterize these pairs of sets without reference to objects, which may be done by the further observation that, if we have two sets and of morphisms such that
if and only if is defined for all
and
if and only if is defined for all
, then there exists an object which gives rise to and as above. This fact may be demonstrated easily enough from the usual definition of category. We will now reverse the procedure, using our axioms to show that such pairs behave as objects should, justifying defining objects as such pairs.
Returning to our new definition, let us now define
,
,
, and
as follows:
We now show that, if
then either
or . Suppose that
and
. Then there exists a morphism such that and . By the definition of , there exist morphisms and such that
and
. By definition of , we have
and
. If , then
so, by axiom 1,
, i.e.
. Likewise, switching the roles of and we conclude that, if , then . Hence .
Making an argument similar to that of last paragraph, but with instead of and instead of , we also conclude that, if
then either
or . Because of axiom 3a, we know that, for every , there exists such that
and, by axiom 3b, there exists such that
. Hence, the sets and are each partitions of .
Next, we show that, if
and , then
. By definition, there exists a morphism such that
, so
and
. Now suppose that
. This means that
. By axiom 1, we conclude that
, so
. Likewise, switching the roles of and in the foregoing argument, we conclude that, if
, then
. Thus,
.
By a similar argument to that of the last paragraph, we may also show that, if
and , then
. Taken together, these results tell us that there is a one-to-one correspondence between of and — to each
, there exists exactly one
such that
and vice-versa. In light of this fact, we shall define and object of our category to be a pair of subsets of such that if and only if
for all and if and only if
for all . Given two objects and , we define
. We now will verify that, with these definitions, our axioms reproduce the defining properties of the standard definition of category.
Suppose that and and are objects according to the above definition and that
and
. Then and . By the way we defined our pairs,
, so is defined. Let be any element of . Since , it follows that
. Since
as well, it follows from axiom 2 that
, so
. Let be any element of . Since , it follows that
. Since
as well, it follows from axiom 2 that
, so
. Hence,
. Thus, is defined as a function from
.
Next, suppose that and are distinct objects. By the properties described earlier,
and
. Let and be two objects. Since
and
, it follows that
. Likewise, since
and
, it follows that
. Hence, it follows that, given four objects , we have
unless and .
[more to come]
Footnotes
- 1
- For simplicity, we will only consider small categories here, avoiding logical complications related to proper classes.
|